blog:2023-03-04
Differences
This shows you the differences between two versions of the page.
Both sides previous revisionPrevious revisionNext revision | Previous revision | ||
blog:2023-03-04 [2023/03/04 18:05] – [Barr-Beck condition] pzhou | blog:2023-03-04 [2023/06/25 15:53] (current) – external edit 127.0.0.1 | ||
---|---|---|---|
Line 8: | Line 8: | ||
Let me follow [[ https:// | Let me follow [[ https:// | ||
And, Akhil Matthew' | And, Akhil Matthew' | ||
+ | |||
+ | ==== L2 ==== | ||
Category warm-up. | Category warm-up. | ||
Line 48: | Line 50: | ||
Warm-up: what is the filtered colimit in Set? It is a disjoint union of the valued set, quotient out by some realtion. | Warm-up: what is the filtered colimit in Set? It is a disjoint union of the valued set, quotient out by some realtion. | ||
- | Warm-up: what is an arbitrary colimit in Set? For example, how do you take the ' | + | Warm-up: what is an arbitrary colimit in Set? For example, how do you take the ' |
+ | |||
+ | Warm-up: now that I know, in set, limit = global section; colimit = gluing, and filtered colimit = gluing without using lines to connect things. then if I have two indexing categories, a filtered cat $I$ and a finite cat $J$, and a bi-functor $D(i,j)$, then I can either take $J$ direction global section, then patch it up, in the I direction. or I can take the I-direction patching, then take the resulting global section. The second approach is apparently more complicated. The idea is that, for the finite limit of the filtered colimit, for each node $j$, we choose some guy in the termwise colimit, so that they are compatible in the colimit-sense relations. Now, we take representatives back in the finite place. they may each map to some different, but finitely many $i(j)$. We can first let them meet-up downstream at some common node $i$. but then, the arrows between them may not match-up, but we know they evnetually match-up, and there are only finitely many arrows, so we flow downstream, until they one by one all become green-check. So, then, we finished constructed a lift from the global section of the filtered colimit to something easy and nice. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Notation: right-cone of a category $I$: just add a terminal object to $I$. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Say $F: C \to D$ is a functor, we say $F$ preserves and reflect colimit, meaning: suppose we have a candidate colimit diagram in $C$, and take its image in $D$. Then, the diagram is colimit (right exact) in $C$, if and only if it is colimit in $D$. Note that, we don't assume whether all diagrams can be cocompleted to a colimit diagram, either in $C$ and in $D$. I am only saying, the amount of colimit diagram are the same in $C$ and in $D$. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Suppose $U: C \to Set$ is a faithful functor (no hom gets killed, hence no objects get killed), and suppose $U$ matches filtered colimit and finite limit on both sides (no add, no subtract), then finite limit and filtered colimit in $C$ commute. Application: | ||
+ | |||
+ | Finite colimit of compact object is compact. Because say $(B_j)$ is a filtered colimit over $J$, and $A_i$ is a finite colimit over $I$, and we have $A=colim A_i$, $B = colim B_j$, we want to know | ||
+ | $$ Hom(A, colim_j B_j) = lim_i Hom(A_i, colim_j B_j) = lim_i colim_j Hom(A_i, | ||
+ | in the middle, I used the fact that $Hom(A_i, B_j)$ is a set. | ||
+ | |||
+ | A module over a ring $R$ is compact, if and only if it is finitely presented. I can understand finite generation, but don't understand finite presentation. Let me show that such thing are compact. First, $Hom_R(R, -)$ is the same as forgetful functor to abelian group. it is the right-adjoint to Free. $R$ is projective. I want to say it commutes with all colimit. **finite colimit of compact is compact**, hence finite presented is compact. Finally, why every compact is of this form? Can we say, finitely presented sub-objects? | ||
+ | |||
+ | what is a reflexive pair? think of two deformation retraction of $A \rightrightarrows B$, where $B \into A$. ok, it is what it is. | ||
+ | |||
+ | What does co-equalizer mean? Can we say $B$ is the co-equalizer, | ||
+ | |||
+ | ==== L3 ==== | ||
+ | $\gdef\tto{\rightrightarrows}$ | ||
+ | Barr-Beck. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Monad. A monad $T$ in $C$, is an endofunctor with some extra data satisfying some conditions. monad needs a unit and a composition. An endfunctor tells you how to move objects and morphism in a category, so that composition and stuff doesn' | ||
+ | |||
+ | Usually, you give me an adjunction pair $L: C <-> D: R$, we get a monad $T:= RL$ acting on $C$, and we can ask, can we reconstruct $D$ using $R(D)$ as a $Mod_T(C)$? We view $C$ as some weak guy, and we view having these extra data (monad action) constraint what objects you can use. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Sometimes, the dream fails. For examples $L = free: Set < | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | What's the crude Barr-Beck? It says, if you have an adjuction like $$ L: C \leftrightarrow D: R$$ and constructed the monad $T = RL$, then if two conditions are satisfied, then the comparison morphisms $R: D \to Mod_T(C)$ is an equivalence. One condition is really easy to check: $R$ reflect isomorphism; | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | Here is the weirdest definition in the world: split coequalizer. I bearly understand reflexive pair, and its coequalizer; | ||
+ | * $h$ coequalizes $d_0, d_1$ (but may not be the co-equalizer), | ||
+ | * $t: X_0 \to X_1$ can be thought of as an embedding, and $d_0: X_1 \to X_0$ is a projection. | ||
+ | * So, this part is easy to understand: that as vector space, we have nested subspaces with well-chosen complements $$ X_1 = V_1 \oplus V_0 \oplus V_{-1}, \quad X_0 = V_0 \oplus V_{-1}, \quad X_{-1} = V_{-1}. $$ | ||
+ | * What's the condition on the remaining arrow? $d_0$ just kills $V_1$ and is identity on the rest. $d_1: X_1 \to X_0$ (viewed as map to itself), such that when restricted on $X_0$ projects to $X_{-1}$. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | I don't know how to generalize this to many steps. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Let's prove the Barr-Beck (crude version). We have a pair of adjoint functors $L: C <-> D;R$, and $T =RL$, and we assume $R$ is conservative, | ||
+ | |||
+ | Let's assume we have additive category. no need to assume abelian category. If $D$ is an abelian category, and $R$ preserve small colimit, then these conditions are automatically true. | ||
+ | |||
+ | We want to know if $\wt R: D \to Mod_T(C)$ by $c \mapsto R(c )$ is an equivalence or not. | ||
+ | |||
+ | * Step 1: we need to construct a fancy left-adjoint $\wt L: Mod_T(C) \to D$. No, this is not the composition of forget to $C$ and then apply $L$, because hom in $Mod_T(C)$ and in $C$ are quite different. We anticipate $\wt L$ is the inverse, so it should behave more like $R^{-1}$. For example, we expect it to do $\wt L\wt R(d) = d$. However, not every T-module in $C$ is written as $\wt R(d)$. But, no worries, we should be able to resolve, and then strip off the $R$ from the resolution. Suppose $A \in Mod_T(C)$, we have resolution $$ T(T(A)) \rightrightarrows T(A) \xto{m} A $$ So, we should get | ||
+ | $$ LRL(A) | ||
+ | $$ LA \xto{L(1 \to RL)A} LRLA \xto{(LR \to 1)LA} LA$$ is identity. who says so? counit axioms of adjunction says so. The other thing is $A \to TA \to A$ unit compose with action is identity, so again ok. We indeed have a reflexive pair. So, using the requirements, | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | There is a related fact about monad $T$. We have | ||
+ | $$ TA \xto{(1 \to T)(TA)} TTA \xto{(TT \to T)A} TA$$ | ||
+ | this has nothing to do with $A$, purely axioms of monad $T \xto{(1\to T)T} TT \xto{m} T$ is identity. Good, we also have | ||
+ | $$ TA \xto{T(1 \to T) TTA} \xto{T(TA \to A)} TA$$ | ||
+ | which has nothing to do with the left most $T$, which is again identity. | ||
+ | |||
+ | < | ||
+ | WOW, this is wrong, the two maps $T \to TT$ are different, it matter where you insert this $T$. So, we don't have a reflexive pair! | ||
+ | |||
+ | Instead, we have a split pair. | ||
+ | $$ TTA \tto TA \to A $$ | ||
+ | How? $A \to TA$ exists using $1 \to T$. And $TA \to TTA$ append on the leftmost $1 \to T$. So we have the desired embedding. And, it is easy to check that, appending $1$ on the left and actual merge $TA \to A$ commute. Hence this is a split pair. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Hold on, again, this is split in $C$, not in $Mod_T(C)$, indeed, the splitting morphisms are not $T$-module. The action of $T$ on bare $A$ is using real data, and the action of $T$ on $1\cdot A$ is formal. | ||
+ | |||
+ | We need to check that, this sequence, is indeed a coequalizer in $Mod_T(C)$. Not hard. | ||
+ | |||
+ | We can do the sharper version. We know that this pair, $LRLA \tto LA$ in $D$, when apply $R$, becomes | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | * Step 2: show that $id_{Mod_T(C)} \to \wt R \wt L$ is an equivalence. | ||
+ | * Step 3: show that $\wt L \wt R \to id_D$ is an equivalence. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | So, what did I learn? nothing, just write down the correction adjoint with correction. | ||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | |||
+ | |||
blog/2023-03-04.1677953122.txt.gz · Last modified: 2023/06/25 15:53 (external edit)